分类:Measurement of risk attitude
The core question and some background
Risk attitude is quite often a relevant factor in many decision making games/situations. Thus often researchers need to use some kind of standard means to measure of the risk attitude of test subjects. One of these typical methods is the famous Holt&Larry 10 lottery experiment [1][2]: a test subject is asked to choose option A or option B in each of the ten lottery choices, which are shown in more details in the following table.
Option A | Option B | Expected payoff difference | Variation difference | estimated range of [math]\displaystyle{ r }[/math] |
---|---|---|---|---|
1/10 of $2.00, 9/10 of $1.60 | 1/10 of $3.85, 9/10 of $0.10 | $1.17 | -1.25 | |
2/10 of $2.00, 8/10 of $1.60 | 2/10 of $3.85, 8/10 of $0.10 | $0.83 | -2.22 | |
3/10 of $2.00, 7/10 of $1.60 | 3/10 of $3.85, 7/10 of $0.10 | $0.50 | -2.92 | |
4/10 of $2.00, 6/10 of $1.60 | 4/10 of $3.85, 6/10 of $0.10 | $0.16 | -3.34 | |
5/10 of $2.00, 5/10 of $1.60 | 5/10 of $3.85, 5/10 of $0.10 | -$0.18 | -3.48 | |
6/10 of $2.00, 4/10 of $1.60 | 6/10 of $3.85, 4/10 of $0.10 | -$0.51 | -3.34 | |
7/10 of $2.00, 3/10 of $1.60 | 7/10 of $3.85, 3/10 of $0.10 | -$0.85 | -2.92 | |
8/10 of $2.00, 2/10 of $1.60 | 8/10 of $3.85, 2/10 of $0.10 | -$1.18 | -2.22 | |
9/10 of $2.00, 1/10 of $1.60 | 9/10 of $3.85, 1/10 of $0.10 | -$1.52 | -1.25 | |
10/10 of $2.00, 0/10 of $1.60 | 10/10 of $3.85, 0/10 of $0.10 | -$1.85 | 0 |
Option B always has larger variation then option A, however, starting with lower average payoff at the first lottery, average payoffs from option B gradually become higher than that of option A. To see this, we have added each column for difference between average payoffs of option A and option B and also for difference between variations of option A and option B.
For a risk neutral player, who cares only about the average payoff, it is clear that he/she will choose option A for the first 4 lotteries and will choose option B for the latter ones. That is transition point is likely at 4-5 for risk neutral players. Risk aversion players is likely willing to trade some payoff for less variation, thus seems to choose more secure options. In turn, this will make the transition point later than 4-5. Likely, risk seeking players will like to get a high risk option thus start to choose option with larger variations earlier than 4-5. In this sense, the transition point can be used as an indicator of risk attitude.
The underlying theory of Holt&Larry: Expected Utility Theory
This is a very good idea in general to use a set of lotteries to reveal risk attitude. However, there are quite several problems in the details of the above setup. For example, values of the probabilities, might be further adjusted to reach a better measurement. The current setup is related to an underlying theory, so-called Measures of risk aversion under expected utility theory, and in particular constant relative risk aversion (CRRA), where the utility of mixed options are [math]\displaystyle{ U\left(p_{A}|A\rangle \langle A|+p_{B}|B\rangle \langle B|\right)=p_{A}U\left(A\right)+p_{B}U\left(B\right) }[/math] while the utility of a pure option is [math]\displaystyle{ U\left(A\right)=\left[E\left(A\right)\right]^{1-r} }[/math]. Here [math]\displaystyle{ E\left(A\right) }[/math] is the monetary payoff of the pure option A. Note that, ideally, [math]\displaystyle{ r }[/math] should be less than 1 since overall larger monetary payoff often means larger utility too. One can also define risk aversion, neutral and seeking according to this parameter [math]\displaystyle{ r }[/math]: [math]\displaystyle{ r=0 }[/math] for neutral, [math]\displaystyle{ r\gt 0 }[/math] for aversion and [math]\displaystyle{ r\lt 0 }[/math] for seeking.
With this underlying theory, given the transition point [math]\displaystyle{ j }[/math], one can calculate value of r. [math]\displaystyle{ P_{j-1}U(A_{j-1,1})+\left(1-P_{j-1}\right)U(A_{j-1,2})\geq P_{j-1}U(B_{j-1,1})+\left(1-P_{j-1}\right)U(B_{j-1,2}) }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ P_{j}U(A_{j,1})+\left(1-P_{j}\right)U(A_{j,2})\leq P_{j}U(B_{j,1})+\left(1-P_{j}\right)U(B_{j,2}) }[/math]. With these two equations but only one unknown variable [math]\displaystyle{ r }[/math], it is easy to estimate the unknown. It can be seen clearly that in some cases, [math]\displaystyle{ r }[/math] is required to be much over 1. This makes not too much sense.
Besides the linearity, expected utility theory when applied to risk attitude, also assumes the following, [math]\displaystyle{ U^{rn}\left(A\right)=E\left(A\right) }[/math], [math]\displaystyle{ U^{ra}\left(A\right) \lt U^{rn}\left(A\right)=E\left(A\right) }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ U^{rs}\left(A\right) \gt U^{rn}\left(A\right)=E\left(A\right) }[/math]. Discussions on specific forms of [math]\displaystyle{ U^{ra} }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ U^{rs} }[/math] can be found from again Measures of risk aversion under expected utility theory.
However, this is not the most general form of utility function of a mixed option.
The most general utility function of a mixed option
更进一步,为什么想度量出来纯风险厌恶或者喜爱程度、纯收益理性程度呢?
为了将来构建一个综合考虑了收益(均值)和风险(方差或者弥散程度的某种度量)的效用函数,以及一个基于这个效用函数的决策模型。另外,为了这个目的,我们还需要研究一下,风险用什么样的方式进入效用函数——是否用方差来代表是可以的。例如,我们可以让选项A、B的均值方差都一样,但是更高阶矩不同,然后做多次来看被试的选择是不是具有稳定的方向性——例如追求更高或者更低的高阶矩。
更一般地来说,对于一个混合决策[math]\displaystyle{ \rho }[/math],例如[math]\displaystyle{ \rho=P_{A}\left|A\right\rangle\left\langle A\right|+P_{B}\left|B\right\rangle\left\langle B\right| }[/math],我们可以算出开这个混合测略的均值、方差、高阶矩等等,或者至少,效用是这个混合测略的函数,[math]\displaystyle{ U=U\left(\rho\right) }[/math],也有可能是[math]\displaystyle{ U=U\left(E\left(\rho\right),\Delta\left(\rho\right),\eta\left(\rho\right),\cdots \right) }[/math]。
两个理论基础的结合
现在如何把期望效用理论和分布函数的函数(其实是泛函)的数学形式相结合,以及从各阶矩的函数的角度来检验一下,到底函数形式如何,或者至少有哪些变量?这是一个有深远意义的问题。
广义地来看,如果我们允许分布函数的泛函包含货币收益的线性和非线性函数当作效用,则实际上,我们的框架包含了期望收益理论——期望收益相当于仅仅考虑一阶矩[math]\displaystyle{ E\left(\rho\right)=P_{A}U\left(A\right)+P_{B}U\left(B\right) }[/math]。因此,分布函数的泛函的讨论是更加基本的问题。
同时,许彬等人的预实验发现,风险态度——假设可以用一个参数[math]\displaystyle{ \theta }[/math]来描述的话,受到被试的认知负担的影响。因此,实际上,我们是在做关于[math]\displaystyle{ U=U\left(\left. E\left(\rho\right),\Delta\left(\rho\right),\eta\left(\rho\right),\cdots \right|\theta\right) }[/math],或者说[math]\displaystyle{ U=U\left(\left. \rho \right|\theta\right) }[/math]的函数形式的研究。
Experimental Setup
In order to have a better measurement of risk attitude, and also to look into the utility function of mixed options, we propose to do the following:
- options with the same average payoff but different variation, or higher-order moments
- options with the same variation or the same higher-order moments but different average payoff
- other combinations
下一步的工作
- 文献调研,看看更多的风险态度测量的文章,以及风险态度在其他实验中对结果的影响的文献
- 预实验,尝试多种选项调整的设计
- 实验
参考文献
- ↑ Holt, C. A., & Laury, S. K. (2002). Risk aversion and incentive effects. American Economic Review, 92(5), 1644-1655.
- ↑ Gary Charness, Uri Gneezy and Alex Imas, Experimental methods: Eliciting risk preferences, Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 87(2013), 43-51, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jebo.2012.12.023.
引用错误:在<references>
中以“Habib”名字定义的<ref>
标签没有在先前的文字中使用。
引用错误:在<references>
中以“Daniel”名字定义的<ref>
标签没有在先前的文字中使用。
本分类目前不含有任何页面或媒体文件。